5 Phenomenologists
Some of the most fruitful intellectual debates
took place in Germany between World Wars. The complex of ideas
that went under the name 'phenomenology' were generated in an
atmosphere of heightened social conflict and anxiety about the
future. It was Edmund
Husserl who first developed a
phenomenological approach. That mean that he would look at the
phenomena of consciousness, and bracket them from any question of
whether they are true or not. Reflecting on the formal science of
Geometry he came to the conclusion that the objectivity of ideas
arose from their assent amongst a community of subjects. This was
an intellectual development that closely paralleled Wittgenstein's shift from truth tables to language games - but in
Germany, and later in France, the idea got a more sympathetic
reception.
Already the distinction between a realm of
nature and one of culture, with their respective sciences of
Naturwissenschaften and Geisteswissenschaften, had been made in
Germany by Dilthey and his fellow neo-Kantians. This was a
development that helped the growth of sociology in Germany, as
did the influence of Max
Weber. Weber's sociology - in part a
challenge to a burgeoning Marxism - paid special attention to
cultural factors. Amongst Weber's students the precocious
Hungarian Gyorgy
Lukacs embodied the challenge of
Marxism. At the end of the first world war, when Germans were
faced with the choice between a pax Americana or the New World in
the East, Weber and Lukacs parted company as Weber joined the
Weimar government in Germany and Lukacs took part in the brief
Soviet revolution in his native Hungary as minister of culture.
After the war, sociologists like Max Scheler, Alfred Schutz and Karl
Mannheim were increasingly influenced
by the phenomenological approach. Scheler and Mannheim developed Husserl's phenomenology into a 'Sociology of Knowledge' in which
competing points of view were taken as the outcome of competing
sectional interests - it wasn't hard to divine an attempt to
understand the growing dissensus in Wiemar. Schutz linked
Husserl's phenomenology to Weberian sociology, understanding that
if knowledge was generated between subjects then
'intersubjectivity' and the way that it created a 'lifeworld' of
meaning should be the subject of investigation.
However, these investigations were in danger of
being overshadowed by a more violent clash of opinion as Germany
slid into anarchy. The possibilities of constitutional government
and the yearning for dramatic political solutions, the growing
alienation from society, and Germany's future were all issues
that were at large at the time. In philosophy they found a
particularly pointed formulation in the unspoken hostility
between Edmund
Husserl's brilliant student Martin Heidegger and Gyorgy
Lukacs, and the counterposition of
their two political and philosophical tracts: Being and Time
and History and Class Consciousness.
Lukacs had already broken from constitutionalism, in favour of
a bolshevism that even earned him a reprimand from Lenin.
The principle of the masses overrode constitutional democracy.
Also he had reworked Marx's critique of capitalist society, with
elements of the Geisteswissenschaften of Dilthey and Heinrich
Rickert, to analyse the alienation in Western society in his
essay 'Reification and the consciousness of the proletariat'. The
choice facing Germany was the one outlined by Rosa Luxemburg:
'Socialism or barbarism'.
Heidegger was meditating on the same problems as Lukacs,
but drawing on some very different resources. He analysed
alienation as a metaphysical problem. The instrumental
rationality of traditional ontology had separated being from its
rootedness, making it inauthentic, 'thrown' and abstract. Lukacs'
programme was a 'destruction of ontology' - that is a dismantling
of the instrumental reasoning that had separated us from our
primordial being. In Heidegger's estimation Germany was caught
between the pincers of bolshevism in the East and Yankee
capitalism in the West, which, despite their differences were
'metaphysically' the same, operating according to the same
indifference. Heidegger's attitude to the masses was quite
different from Lukacs. Far from providing the resolution of
alienation they were exemplified it as 'das Man', the They. Mass
media and mass democracy were poisoned by the They, by their
'publicness' and their 'idle chatter'. Heidegger had his answer
to Lukacs's bolshevism. According to Heidegger, the impending
disaster facing Germany was a wake-up call to 'take a stand in
history'. This kind of thinking was common on the right, as for
example the reactionary criticism of parliamentarism made by Carl
Schmitt, that would later be characterised as 'decisionism'.
Of course, this is to reduce these two great
thinkers to their political outlooks, when their own influence
arose less from the political content of what they said, as the
more profound theoretical development of their thinking. So, for
example, Lukacs's influence was felt in the sociology of Mannheim, a comparatively conservative political thinker, who
had been part of Lukacs' circle. In the case of Heidegger the contrasts between ostensible political affiliations
and influence were yet greater. Amongst his students were Emmanuel Levinas and Herbert
Marcuse at Freiburg and Hannah Arendt at Marburg. Even Jean-Paul Sartre attended
Heidegger's lectures. Levinas and Arendt (who had an affair with
Heidegger) were both Jews, and all four were ardent critics of
the Nazi party that Heidegger had joined. As we shall see, the
continuing influence of Heidegger's ideas after the defeat of
Hitler and Heidegger's disgrace, comes largely through the
influence of his unsullied students.
One important instance of the way that
philosophical ideas cut across political affiliations was the
work of the Institute of Social research founded by businessman
Felix Weil under the directorship of Carl Grunberg in 1923. What
went on to be called the 'Frankfurt School' was ostensibly on the
far political left, corresponding with the Marx-Engels Institute
in Moscow. But the key figures in the Frankfurt School, Max Horkheimer, who became director in 1930, Theodor Adorno and later Herbert
Marcuse all favoured an unorthodox
reading of Marx. They were particularly interested in Lukacs
and Karl Korsch's rejection of a mainstream, positivist-inspired
Marxism. Following Lukacs they drew upon Weberian sociology, phenomenology and even Heidggerian ontology to 'enrich' Marxism. But departing from
Lukacs, the School gradually dispensed with the role of the
working class in revolutionary theory, bringing its newly minted
'critical theory' yet closer to Heidegger's romantic rejection of
the modern world. In time it would become clear that the
affiliations of the Frankfurt School gave it a leftist veneer,
but that the content of its work was much closer to the currents
of German philosophy and sociology in the twenties.
Impact of War
The Second World War was a turning point in the
intellectual history of the twentieth century. For those whose
political beliefs or racial origins made it impossible to stay in
Germany and Austria it means upheaval: Carnap
went to Chicago, Popper
to New Zealand, before joining Hayek
in London, Goedel to Chicago, Adorno went first to Oxford - as did Mannheim - and then to Princeton, Lukacs went to Moscow to an
uneasy relationship with the authorities, Freud and
Melanie Klein went to London, Arendt and Karen Horney to New York, Levi-Strauss
to Sao Paulo, Althusser was imprisoned, as was Sartre, briefly, who continued
his underground activities on release. Most ambitiously the
Frankfurt Institute reconvened itself on America's West Coast.
There was a knock-on impact upon intellectuals in Britain and
America who suddenly found themselves next to the best brains of
Europe. For the New School for Social Research in New York this
was clearly an unmitigated success, as the college became an
organising centre for the most advanced ideas in philosophy,
social anthropology and sociology, with Levi-Strauss, Alfred Schutz, and Hannah Arendt joining the faculty. Perry Anderson
suggests that the effect in British Universities was less useful,
dwarfing the achievements of the analytical philosophers, and
inculcating a sense of inferiority towards positivists like Hayek
and Popper.
For those Germans who stayed, however, the
upheaval came not in 1933 with the accession of the Nazis to
power, or 1939 with the outbreak of war, but in 1943 when the
reversal of the German campaign in the East made it obvious that
the Axis powers would lose. German intellectuals who had
supported the Nazis faced the same ignominious trial as other
collaborators with the regime. The party ideologue Rosenberg was
executed, the architect and armaments minister Albert Speer was
imprisoned for twenty years. Behind the front-line of war crimes
trials were the local denazification hearings organised by the
occupying allied powers, before which academics like Carl Schmitt
and Martin
Heidegger were judged.
Schmitt spent a year in the internment camps
and was interrogated, but still managed to evade responsibility
for defending the legality of the Nazi regime, and was allowed to
retire. But unlike Shmitt, Martin Heidegger still
considered himself a player in the intellectual world and fought
tooth and nail to avoid responsibility for his political
affiliations. The terms of Heidegger's defence before the
commission on 23 July 1945 can be surmised from his article
written at the time 'Facts and Thoughts'. There he attempts to
differentiate himself from the Nazis by redefining Fascism in
terms of his own analysis of the mass societies of America and
the Soviet Union: 'the rule and the shape of the worker
is
the universal rule of the will to power within history, now
understood to embrace the planet. Today everything stands in this
historical reality, no matter whether it is called communism, or
fascism, or world democracy.' (Rockmore, p94)
Just as Heidegger assimilated Fascism
to democracy as the 'will to power' of 'the worker', so too did
he relativise the difference between industry and the gas
chambers in a lecture given in 1949: 'Agriculture is now a
mechanised food industry; in essence it is no different from the
production of corpses in the gas chambers and death camps, the
embargoes and food reductions to starving countries, the making
of Hydrogen bombs.' (The Question Concerning Technology, cited in
Lyotard, Heidegger and the 'jews', p85) By these inversions
Heidegger maintained the consistency of his hostility to mass
society and to 'instrumental reason', by turning Fascism from the
proposed resolution of these dangers into an exemplar of them.
In their own mouths Heidegger and Schmitt's evasions were unconvincing. Nobody wanted
to hear their excuses. But the Heideggerian philosophy did
survive the Second World War in the writings of Heidegger's
left-wing, and therefore uncompromised students.
German exiles in America
Hannah Arendt, Herbert
Marcuse, Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer developed the twin theses of 'Totalitarianism' and the
inhumanity of instrumental rationality in America in their books On
Totalitarianism (1951) and Dialectic of
Enlightenment (1944). In the Dialectic of Enlightenment,
technical rationality is held to lead inexorably from the
domination of man of nature to the domination of man over man. It
is an idea that is taken from Being and Time, reworked in
a left-wing style. Anticipating, perhaps informing Heidegger's own apologia, Adorno and Horkheimer see instrumental
reason leading inexorably to the gas chambers - an argument that
has become a central component of modern environmentalism. Their
critique of the mass culture industry (The culture industry:
enlightenment as mass deception') is also inspired in part by
Heidegger's concepts of the 'publicness' and 'idle chatter' of
'the They', except now the power of mass propaganda is identified
with Fascism rather than democracy.
(The strangest story of all was the love affair between the Nazi
Martin Heidegger and his Jewish student Heidegger and Arendt in love)
Arendt's On Totalitarianism also deploys key Heideggerian concepts, albeit to an ostensibly different political
goal. Explaining the power of totalitarian movements Arendt makes
special play of their mass character, a category which closely
parallels Heidegger's Das Man, being characterised by
'indifference' and 'sheer numbers' (p 311). Arendt's contribution
to Cold War ideology is the identification of Soviet Communism
and Fascism under the heading of Totalitarianism - again an
evasion that mirrors Heidegger's own.
6 Existentialists